The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective
Данная статья посвящена анализу научных подходов Канта и Гоббса к идее общественного договора и их влиянию на концепцию справедливости. В статье раскрыто взаимоотношение указанных подходов с двумя разными моделями общественного договора. Показана роль теорий общественного договора в процессе развит...
Gespeichert in:
Datum: | 2005 |
---|---|
1. Verfasser: | |
Format: | Artikel |
Sprache: | English |
Veröffentlicht: |
Інститут держави і права ім. В.М. Корецького НАН України
2005
|
Schlagworte: | |
Online Zugang: | http://dspace.nbuv.gov.ua/handle/123456789/11899 |
Tags: |
Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
|
Назва журналу: | Digital Library of Periodicals of National Academy of Sciences of Ukraine |
Zitieren: | The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective / W. Załuski // Проблеми філософії права. — 2005. — Т. III. — С. 278-285. — Бібліогр.: 12 назв. — англ. |
Institution
Digital Library of Periodicals of National Academy of Sciences of Ukraineid |
irk-123456789-11899 |
---|---|
record_format |
dspace |
spelling |
irk-123456789-118992010-10-26T17:12:16Z The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective Załuski, W. Аксіологія права: принципи свободи, рівності і справедливості Данная статья посвящена анализу научных подходов Канта и Гоббса к идее общественного договора и их влиянию на концепцию справедливости. В статье раскрыто взаимоотношение указанных подходов с двумя разными моделями общественного договора. Показана роль теорий общественного договора в процессе развития понятия справедливости. Автор указал, что относительно теорий общественного договора справедливость может рассматриваться или как взаимная выгода или как беспристрастность. The present article is dedicated to the analysis of the Kantian and the Hobbesian approaches to the idea of the social contract and their influence on the concept of justice. The correlation of these approaches with two different models of the social contract has been shown. The role of the contractarian theories in the process of explication of the notion of justice has been demonstrated. The author points out that according to the contractarian theories justice can be realized either as the mutual advantage or as the impartiality. 2005 Article The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective / W. Załuski // Проблеми філософії права. — 2005. — Т. III. — С. 278-285. — Бібліогр.: 12 назв. — англ. 1818-992X http://dspace.nbuv.gov.ua/handle/123456789/11899 en Інститут держави і права ім. В.М. Корецького НАН України |
institution |
Digital Library of Periodicals of National Academy of Sciences of Ukraine |
collection |
DSpace DC |
language |
English |
topic |
Аксіологія права: принципи свободи, рівності і справедливості Аксіологія права: принципи свободи, рівності і справедливості |
spellingShingle |
Аксіологія права: принципи свободи, рівності і справедливості Аксіологія права: принципи свободи, рівності і справедливості Załuski, W. The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective |
description |
Данная статья посвящена анализу научных подходов Канта и Гоббса к идее общественного договора и их влиянию на концепцию справедливости. В статье раскрыто взаимоотношение указанных
подходов с двумя разными моделями общественного договора. Показана роль теорий общественного договора в процессе развития понятия справедливости. Автор указал, что относительно теорий общественного договора справедливость может рассматриваться или как взаимная выгода или как беспристрастность. |
format |
Article |
author |
Załuski, W. |
author_facet |
Załuski, W. |
author_sort |
Załuski, W. |
title |
The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective |
title_short |
The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective |
title_full |
The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective |
title_fullStr |
The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective |
title_full_unstemmed |
The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective |
title_sort |
concept of justice from the contractarian perspective |
publisher |
Інститут держави і права ім. В.М. Корецького НАН України |
publishDate |
2005 |
topic_facet |
Аксіологія права: принципи свободи, рівності і справедливості |
url |
http://dspace.nbuv.gov.ua/handle/123456789/11899 |
citation_txt |
The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective / W. Załuski // Проблеми філософії права. — 2005. — Т. III. — С. 278-285. — Бібліогр.: 12 назв. — англ. |
work_keys_str_mv |
AT załuskiw theconceptofjusticefromthecontractarianperspective AT załuskiw conceptofjusticefromthecontractarianperspective |
first_indexed |
2025-07-02T14:02:43Z |
last_indexed |
2025-07-02T14:02:43Z |
_version_ |
1836544125405495296 |
fulltext |
АКСІОЛОГІЯ ПРАВА: ПРИНЦИПИ СВОБОДИ, РІВНОСТІ І СПРАВЕДЛИВОСТІ
278 Проблеми філософії права. – 2005. – Том III. – № 1-2.
© 2005 W. Załuski
Institute of the Philosophy of Law Krakow, Poland
THE CONCEPT OF JUSTICE FROM
THE CONTRACTARIAN PERCPECTIVE
1. Introductory remarks
The concept of justice occupies a central position
in the philosophy of law and in political philosophy.
However, owing to its complexity as well as its sus-
ceptibility to ideologically tainted interpretations, the
concept is seldom clearly understood. Nevertheless,
the misunderstandings connected with the concept of
justice can be at least partly avoided provided one
makes an appeal to contractarian theories, i.e., the
theories making use of the idea of the social contract.
This article’s purpose is to provide an overview of
contemporary versions of contractarianism. More spe-
cifically, we shall be concerned with the following top-
ics: (1) The place of contractarianism in practical phi-
losophy∗. (2) The differences between the traditional and
the contemporary contractarianism. (3) Two opposed
approaches (Kantian and Hobbesian) in the contempo-
rary contractarianism. (4) The proper model of the so-
cial contract.
In our presentation we shall put a stress on the fun-
damental controversy between the adherents of the
contractarian approach – namely whether justice is to
be understood as mutual advantage (the Hobbesian
approach) or as impartiality (the Kantian approach)
1. The place of contractarianism in practical
philosophy
The principal idea of any contractarian theory
might be stated as follows: an action, a social practice,
a political institution or a law is permissible provided
it, or principles upon which it is based, would be
agreed to by the agents under appropriately deter-
mined conditions**. If the object of agreement are
principles, then the contractarian theory is indirect,
otherwise it is direct. Most contemporary contractari-
ans interpret the social contract as a hypothetical one,
i.e., as the one that would be made under suitable cir-
cumstances, not as an actual one; on the former inter-
pretation, the idea of the social contract is an analyti-
∗ We use this term in a free manner viz. as embracing
moral, legal and political philosophy.
** See Vallentyne 2001, p.3.
cal device to assess human actions, institutions and
practices. The general idea of contractarianism being
presented, we can compare it with its main rival
among ethical metatheories – namely philosophical
utilitarianism.
At the outset, it should be noted that every moral
theory is to fulfill two functions***: (1) to provide an
account of the foundations of moral reasoning, i.e., to
answer the question about the subject matter of moral-
ity**** and (2) to offer a plausible theory of human
motivation to comply with moral rules, i.e., to account
for the fact that moral considerations are in great
measure determinative of human actions. How do
both metatheories solve these problems?
The adherents of philosophical utilitarianism claim
that (1) the subject matter of morality are facts about
individual wellbeing and that (2) our motivation to act
in accordance with moral rules is a consequence of
our ability to identify with the good of other people. It
should be noted that philosophical utilitarianism dif-
fers essentially from normative utilitarianism in that
while the former is an ethical metatheory, the latter is
an ethical theory, i.e., a set of moral rules or simply
one fundamental rule of conduct. As is well known,
the main demand of normative utilitarianism is that
people act in a way that maximizes aggregate social
welfare. It is worth noting that a theory of the social
contract may serve as a justification of normative
utilitarianism*****.
The defenders of the contractarian approach main-
tain that (1) the foundations of moral reasoning are
determined by the agreement concluded (or which
would be concluded) by individuals willing to gain
the benefits of cooperation and that (2) our sense of
obligation to comply with moral rules can be ac-
counted for by our having agreed to these rules. Of
*** See Scanlon 1983, pp. 104-105.
**** Kymlicka (1998a, p. 226) says that the first task of
a moral theory is to point at norms that should be ob-
served; as we see, this view differs slightly from that of
Scanlon who writes that a moral theory should define a
subject matter of morality.
***** A good example is Harsanyi’s utilitarian theory
(see Harsanyi, 1976, 1977).
W. Zaluski
Проблеми філософії права. – 2005. – Том III. – № 1-2. 279
course, (2) applies only to those theories that take the
social contract to be an actual one. It can, however, be
reformulated in such a way that it will embrace hypo-
thetical contracts as well. It suffices to assume two
theses – namely that a given theory of the hypotheti-
cal social contract generates a principle of justice and
that human beings are concerned with being able to
justify their actions. Then, it is plausible to argue that
the morality’s motivational force lies in the fact that
people desire to be able to justify their actions to other
parties on grounds that could be reasonably accepted
by all parties or could not be reasonably rejected by
these parties. Given the fact that the contract is a hy-
pothetical one, it should be added that the justification
in question is an ideal one, which means that an agent
should not be concerned with the fact that some peo-
ple reject the grounds she provides to justify her ac-
tions if only she knows that such a justification does
exist, i.e., if she knows that were all people to satisfy
the ideal conditions imposed on the agreement they
would accept her justification.
To sum up, it seems that the idea of social contract
provides plausible grounds for morality: it implies that
“the justificatory status of moral properties”∗ and
their motivational appeal are derivative of the idea of
the rational agreement.
Now that the general remarks on contractarianism
and philosophical utilitarianism have been made, we
can examine more closely the notion of the social con-
tract.
2. Two types of contractarianism∗∗
The traditional contractarianism
It was in the17th and in the18th centuries that the
social contract became one of the central notions of
political philosophy. The rationale of having intro-
duced this concept was that the traditional ways of
justifying citizens’ obedience to the state authority
based on the ideas of the natural or the divine order
were no longer acceptable. The concept of the social
contract gave an alternative justification of citizens’
obedience. It implied that having concluded the
agreement to form the political power, individuals
assumed a promise to obey it on condition that the
power respected and protected their natural rights.
As we see, the traditional versions of contractarianism
were political, i.e., they were to justify the state’s exis-
tence and to determine citizens’ obligations towards
the state. The social contract was frequently inter-
∗ This is Scanlon’s expression (see 1982, p.116).
∗∗ See Kymlicka 1998a, pp.226-237, Hampton 2002,
pp. 495-500 and Atger 1906.
preted as the actual agreement, i.e., as the agreement
concluded at a historical time by the agents determined
to leave the state of nature and to found society.
The traditional interpretation of the social contract
has been criticized for multiple reasons. As has been
shown, on this interpretation, the social contract rests
on the theory of natural rights and duties: the state is
obliged to protect the citizens’ rights, who – on their
part – ought to keep their promises to observe the con-
tract resolutions. Considering, however, that the the-
ory of natural rights and natural duties*** is question-
able, one could plausibly argue that the theory of so-
cial contract – the response to the decline of the pre-
Enlightenment ethics – replaced one doubtful type of
duties (i.e., the divine ones) by the other being equally
controversial (i.e., the natural duties). Another objec-
tion pressed against the traditional contractarianism
was that the social contract had never been concluded.
The consequences of this fact seemed to be especially
troubling: assuming that without the agreement hav-
ing been made, no authority can be called a legal one,
it had to be admitted that there are no obligations
binding the citizens and the government. Conse-
quently, all the governmental institutions were to be
regarded as deprived of legal validity. One attempted
to evade these consequences by inventing the concept
of the hypothetical contract, i.e., the contract that
would have been concluded by the agents had they
found themselves in some kind of the state of na-
ture****. On this interpretation, the social contract was
understood not as a historical explanation of the ori-
gins of a political power, but simply as the manner in
which one can speak about conditions under which
the government may have the authority over citizens..
However, this approach was found out to be useless as
a way of justifying political obligations, for the simple
reason that contracts can be considered as a source of
obligation only if they were really concluded – as
Dworkin says: “a hypothetical contract is not simply a
pale form of an actual contract; it is no contract at
all”*. Therefore, a fictitious contract cannot account
for real duties.
*** The natural duty presupposed by the theory of the
social contract is the requirement to keep promises.
**** In fact, the theorists of the social contract (e.g.,
Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau) early understood that the
contractarian ideas make sense only if one interprets the
social contract as the hypothetical agreement. It can be
added that one of the most severe critics of the social
contract as the actual agreement was Hume.
* Dworkin 1978, p.18.
The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective
280 Проблеми філософії права. – 2005. – Том III. – № 1-2.
To conclude, the traditional versions of the social
contract which were to provide a justification of po-
litical obligations are open to three main objections:
first, if one assumes that that the only justification of
political obligations towards the state derives from the
actual contract concluded by citizens, then, given the
fact that no such contract was in fact made, one has to
admit that these obligations are groundless; second,
the social contract interpreted as the hypothetical
agreement cannot generate obligations; third, the tra-
ditional contractarianism assumes natural rights,
which themselves need to be justified.
The contemporary contractarianism
Contemporarily, the social contract is conceived of
as a hypothetical agreement being an analytical device
to highlight the essence of morality** and to assess
social institution, practices or individual actions.
Therefore, the contemporary contractarianism tackles
the problem of grounding personal – moral – duties
which were taken for granted by the traditional ver-
sion; it is, therefore, to realize in some sense a mo-re
ambitious task than the one faced by its older coun-
terpart, which was primarily to justify the obedience
to and the legitimacy of the state.
Contemporary theorists of the social contract put
a stress on two elements: first, on the fact that obliga-
tions are conventional, i.e., that they result from a co-
operation of equal human beings; second, on the fact
that conventional duties in some satisfy human inter-
ests. Therefore, the essence of the social contract in its
contemporary version consists in determining conven-
tions which advance human interests. What does it,
however, mean that human beings are equal? How is
the phrase “advance human interests” to be under-
stood? To answer these questions precisely, we shall
have to distinguish two main currents of the contem-
porary contractarianism.
3. Justice: impartiality or mutual advantage?
The contemporary theories of the social contract
can be neatly divided into two groups depending on
which conception of equality of men they presup-
pose***:
** In particular, the essence of justice (it can be noted
that, e.g., Rawls takes the social contract as a method of
defining justice, while Scanlon as a method of deter-
mining moral obligations).
*** See Kymlicka 1998a and 1998b,respectively,
pp.229-231, pp. 145-153, and Hampton 2002, p.495-498.
(1) the Kantian theories of social contract – justice
as impartiality: based upon the idea of moral equal-
ity of men.
(2) the Hobbesian theories social contract – justice
as mutual advantage: based upon the idea of natural
equality of men, i.e., the equality of physical and
psychological forces.
Each group offers an entirely different view on the
essence of morality, in particular – on the essence of
justice. However, before we pass to analyzing these
differences, we shall first present the assumptions
both approaches share.
Both types of contractarianism assume that society
exists for the mutual benefit of its members. They
presuppose the idea of the social contract as described
in the following passage:
The social contract represents the agreement one
would have made in an initial state of nature, in order
to enter civil society. It does not represent the agree-
ment one would now make, within civil society, in
order to continue in this condition. Nor does it repre-
sent the agreement one would in hindsight have made,
at the time of entry into civil society, could one have
known the consequences. One must eliminate from
considerations all information which could have been
acquired only subsequently to entry into society, in
determining what agreement would have been rational
for one to make in the initial state of nature****.
The underlying ideology of both versions of the
social contract is individualistic: society is regarded as
a conventional entity and as an instrument for realiz-
ing individual ends of its members rather than deter-
mining these ends. The parties to the contract are con-
sidered to be mutually unconcerned, i.e., without
other-regarding desires. Both versions treat the social
contract as a hypothetical one. The aim of the social
contract to determine a principle for cooperative ac-
tion (interpreted as a principle of justice – Rawls, or
as morality tout court – Gauthier).
Now we can examine the differences between both
approaches.
Ad.1 Kantian theorists of the social contract as-
sume the intrinsic value of each individual, or, as Kant
put it, each individual’s being ‘an end-in-itself’. (They
make, therefore, some assumptions concerning moral-
ity prior to using the notion of social contract*). The
role of the social contract is to ascertain how thus
characterized people ought to be treated. In this con-
text, the fundamental concept of the social contract
proves to be that of impartiality which requires that
**** Gauthier 1978, p.49.
* Which reveals a simplifying character of our general
description of the contemporary contractarianism.
W. Zaluski
Проблеми філософії права. – 2005. – Том III. – № 1-2. 281
each individual has the right to equal treatment (to
‘equal concern and respect’**). The social contract,
therefore, epitomizes the basic principle of the impar-
tial judgment which demands that everyone should
take into account needs of others as of free and equal
human beings.
A good illustration of the Kantian approach to the
idea of the social contract is Scanlon’s contractarian
definition of a wrong act:
An act is wrong if its performance under the cir-
cumstances would be disallowed by any system of
rules for the general regulation of behavior which no
one could reasonably reject as a basis for informed,
unforced, general agreement***.
Of course, there are very serious differences be-
tween Kant’s original moral theory and the theories
of, e.g., Scanlon, Rawls or Harsanyi as well as be-
tween the latter theories themselves. Nevertheless, the
presence in these theories of such notions as moral
person, generalisability, the right to equal treatment,
freedom, ethical preferences, overcoming one’s self in-
terest (or to use Kantian terms, one’s empirical motives)
entitles one to take those otherwise various theories as
belonging to one group. Some more remarks are needful
with reference to the Kantian approach.
It is worth noting that the adherents of the Kantian
tradition replace the picture of the state of nature as
‘the war of all against all’ with the situation of equal-
ity in which every party is to take into account the
interests of the other parties. The state of nature****,
therefore, represents the equality of human beings as
persons in the moral sense. Accordingly, the social
contract leads to accepting some version of the equal-
ity of rights and resources.
Of course, various principles may fulfill the above
general conditions of a ‘Kantian’ contractarian theory.
Therefore, in order that more definite answers to the
question about ‘the right rules of conduct’ be gained,
it is necessary to impose some additional conditions
on the type of agreement to be made and on the crite-
ria of rationality to be used. Now, the most sophisti-
cated tool that may prove helpful while realizing this
task is the theory of rational choice including game the-
ory and decision theory. As will be shown in the next
section, it is decision theory that can be particularly use-
ful for Kantian theorists of the social contract.
As has been mentioned, one of the tasks of each
moral theory is to provide an account of human moti-
** See Dworkin 1978, p. 50.
*** Scanlon 1983, p.110.
**** Rawls avoids this term speaking instead about the
original position (see Rawls 1973, pp. 17-22).
vation to act morally. It turns out that the Kantian
theories run into serious difficulties in the face of this
task. One of their basic assumptions is that a truly
moral action ought to be motivated solely by the
agent’s intellectual understanding of the reasons that
stand behind moral rules, not by her subjective prefer-
ences. Needless to say, the thesis that understanding
alone has a motivational force is very controversial.
Ad.2. The defenders of the Hobbesian approach to
the idea of the social contract claim that human beings
have only instrumental value. This claim entails the
rejection of the crucial notions of Kantian philoso-
phers (e.g., the notion of a man as an ‘end-in-itself) as
fictions that prevent rational grounding of morality.
The Hobbesian approach to the social contract
rests on the supposition that morality can be grounded
in instrumental rationality, i.e., that can be derived
from non-moral premises. Therefore, while within the
Kantian theories morality is constructed from the
moral premises concerning human reason*****, within
the Hobbesian theories morality is interpreted as in-
vented to maximize human beings preference satisfac-
tion, or – at best – as inferred from non-moral prem-
ises******.
The Hobbesian theories assume that the potential
parties to the contract will reach it provided they re-
frain from the direct pursuit of their self-interest. The
state in which individuals put no constraints on the
maximization of their prefernces is the Hobbesian
‘war of all against all’, or, to use a modern terminol-
ogy, the state in which only suboptimal equilibria can be
reached – the state that rational individuals will be will-
ing to leave by concluding the social contract.
As for the philosophical assumptions of the Hob-
besian approach, it should be noted that Hobbesian
philosophers deny the existence of objective values.
They claim that all one can reasonably speak about as
regards morality are subjective preferences of indi-
viduals. Accordingly, they affirm that there is no natu-
ral distinction between good and evil. They concede,
though, that it may advantageous for the promotion of
our interests to establish a convention that condemns
certain deeds (e.g., killing, lying) as evil. In this view,
therefore, morality is a mode of cooperation which
should be accepted voluntarily by all rational people,
since it advances their interests.
The defenders of this controversial view claim that
in the world in which there are no objective values
and natural obligations morality as mutual advantage
***** The Kantian theories, as has been mentioned, assume
some moral notions (e.g., that of moral person etc.).
****** See Hampton 2001, pp.50-53.
The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective
282 Проблеми філософії права. – 2005. – Том III. – № 1-2.
is the best thing that we may have, i.e. we have no
alternative but to content ourselves with the existence
of a moral code that is the effect of mutually benefi-
cial conventions. The conventions that arise as a result
of negotiations among parties will reflect the differ-
ences in their bargaining forces (by contrast, Kantian
philosophers claim that the aim of the social contract
is to negate the existence of differences as regards the
bargaining forces of parties). The content of the con-
ventions having arisen in consequence of bargaining
will correspond with traditional moral norms provided
that parties have equal bargaining forces, i.e., that they
are in fact equal; otherwise, i.e., if there is a dispro-
portion in these forces, the outcome is bound to be
disadvantageous for the weakest individuals, which
violates our moral intuitions. What’s more, it may be
plausibly argued that given the fact that each individ-
ual has the right to make use of all resources at her
disposal, moral norms will emerge only if these indi-
viduals have approximately equal capacities, since
otherwise ‘stronger’ parties will not be motivated to
leave the state of nature. Understandably, the notion
of inalienable rights to which an individual is entitled
independently of her bargaining force is incompre-
hensible on the ground of the Hobbesian theories.
As for the motivational function of morality, Hob-
besian philosophers assume that people are motivated
to undertake moral actions only if these actions satisfy
some of their desires. Accordingly, they claim that the
fact that compliance with moral norms accepted by
the parties to the social contract increases in the log
run their chance of satisfying their preferences pro-
vides a clear account of human motivation to act mor-
ally.
As can be easily inferred from the above consid-
erations, the adherents of the Hobbesian approach to
the idea of the social contract claim that the same cri-
teria of rationality and objectivity should be applied
both in the sphere of moral reflection and in other
spheres of human knowledge. Such an assumption
excludes of course Kantian reflections about moral
equality of human beings (or about the natural right to
equal concern and respect) from the area of rational
discourse. What is at issue is whether we should
require that morality should satisfy the same crite-
ria of objectivity and rationality as those satisfied
by ‘more exact’ disciplines. Thus, we see that the
fundamental philosophical controversy within contrac-
tarian theories boils down to the old controversy be-
tween naturalism (represented, e.g., by Hobbes) and
anti-naturalism (represented, e.g., by Kant).
Summing up, within the Hobbesian tradition, the
notion of morality gains an entirely different meaning
as compared with a traditional one. What’s more, it
may be plausibly argued that the Hobbesian theo-
ries of the social contract do not represent an al-
ternative conception of morality, but an alternative
to morality∗.
The last question to be answered in this section is
whether the theories of the social contract really base
morality on the notion of agreement∗∗. As regards its
traditional versions, the answer is positive, though
a reservation must be made that an underlying as-
sumption of these theories is the thesis that there exist
natural obligations. As regards the contemporary con-
tractarianism, the matter is even more complicated:
although prima facie the notion of the social contract
may seem to be of great moment, as it is believed to
provide the foundation of justice, it may be plausibly
argued that this notion is no more than an analytical
device to explicate impartiality and mutual advantage
which are the real foundations of morality∗∗∗.
In the next section we will show that the two ap-
proaches to the social contract discussed above can be
correlated with two different models of the social con-
tract.
4. The social contract: an ideal in dividual
decision or an ideal social bargain?
One of the sources of controversies connected with
the notion of the social contract is that it is by no
means clear what conditions should be imposed on the
contract as well as on the parties to it; more specifi-
cally, one must decide whether the social contract
should be modeled as an ideal individual decision
(IID) or as an ideal collective bargain (ICB)****. As
will turn out, this distinction, strictly connected with
the distinction analysed in the previous section, can be
interpreted as derivative of the amount of information
available to parties at the moment of entering the so-
cial contract.
We shall compare both models of the social con-
tract in the table.
Points of
diver-
gence
The social con-
tract as an ideal
collective bargain
The social contract
as an ideal individ-
ual decision
∗ See Kymlicka 1998b, p. 151.
∗∗ See Kymlicka 1998a, p. 236.
∗∗∗ This thesis is defended by Kymlicka (see ibid., pp.
236-237).
**** See Gauthier 1978. A bargain is a situation in
which two or more agents are able to produce some bene-
fit through cooperating with each other on condition that
they agree in advance on a division between them (See
Hargreaves Heap, Varoufakis, 1996, p. 111).
W. Zaluski
Проблеми філософії права. – 2005. – Том III. – № 1-2. 283
1. The par-
ties to the
contract
Only those persons
whose cooperation
may benefit at least
some other persons,
which means, e.g.,
that children and the
severely disabled
cannot be parties to
the contract.
Each person as a moral
person is a party to the
contract. Since all moral
persons are identical, the
social contract can be
thought of as a IID.
2.The re-
quired level
of the igno-
rance of the
parties
Gauthier: no veil of
ignorance – the so-cial
contract is a bargain
among real persons
who are ful-ly in-
formed, deter-minate
and who know their
utility functions*.
Rawls: a thick veil of
ignorance: a decision-
maker lacks the knowl-
edge of her particular
self; she knows only that
she has certain abilities,
certain interests and that
she uses the former to
maximize the satisfaction
of the latter (she has also
the knowledge of the
laws of nature and of
some general features of
the world) Therefore, the
decision-maker – a moral
person – does not know
her utility function.
Scanlon: parties have
full knowledge of their
particular features, yet
they cannot make use
of it – the only motive
of their actions is the
desire to reach a ra-
tional agreement.
3. Notable
contempo-
rary repre-
sentatives.
David Gauthier
(“Morals by Agree-
ment”), James Bu-
chanan (“The Limits
of Liberty”)
John Rawls (“A Theory
of Justice”), John Har-
sanyi (“Rational Be-
havior and
Bargaining Equilib-
rium in Games and
Social Situations”),
Thomas Scanlon
(“Contractualism and
Utiltarianism”)
4. The main
tool of
analysis
Game theory Decision theory
5.The chosen
principles of
justice
Gauthier: the mini-
max relative con-
cession principle
Harsanyi: the avera-
geutilitarian principle,
Rawls: the difference
(maximin) principle**
6. The in-
terpretation of
justice
Mutual advantage Impartiality***
* See Vallentyne., p. 4.
** Scanlon does not formulate a principle of justice; he
provides instead what he calls “a contractualist account
of moral wrongness” (1983, p. 110); its full formulation
can be found above in the text in the section 3.
*** Rawls defines justice as fairness. We identify
fairness with impartiality, though we must admit that it is
a slightly simplifying assumption, since the notion of
7. Philoso-
phical back-
ground
The Hobbesian ap-
proach
The Kantian (Rawls,
Scanlon) or the utilitar-
ian (Harsanyi) ap-
proach
8. The main
objection
Incompatibility with
our moral intuiti-
ons: since parties are
fully informed about
their capacities and
particular situations,
they can make use of
it in a bargain, with
the re-sult that the
‘stron-ger’ parties
will ac-quire a
greater share of the
benefits than the
‘weaker’ ones.
The lack of motiva-
tional force: a real per-
son cannot identify her
present self with the
chooser in the hypo-
thetical state of nature,
since there is no real
individual in the state
of nature (as regards
Harsanyi’s theory) or
the real individual is
arbitrarily chosen (‘the
least advantaged per-
son’ in Rawls’ theory)
Comments on some controversial points.
Ad.1. The adherents the ICB approach defend
their claim by pointing out that the rational agreement
implies each party’s ability to offer benefits to other
parties.
Ad.2. The level of ignorance explains why the so-
cial contract can be conceived of as an individual de-
cision: since the parties do not know difference be-
tween them and each of them is equally rational and
similarly situated, the choice in the state of nature can
be viewed as made by one person randomly selected
from the society****. As we see, the social contract can
be interpreted as IID provided the individuals are re-
garded not as real persons with varied preferences, but
as moral persons who are identical in respect of their
right to equal concern and respect.
Ad.5. Given point 2, it should be understandable
that if one demonstrates that a randomly selected
agent chooses a given principle, one may conclude
that all rational agents would choose the same princi-
ple. The chosen principle constitutes the content of the
social contract as viewed by the adherents of the IID
interpretation.
Harsanyi’s principle differs from classical utilitari-
anism in that while the latter prescribes maximization
of total happiness (utility), the former prescribes
maximization of average utility∗. As for Rawls, his
well known principle is as follows:
fairness contains elements of selfinterest and reciprocity,
from which the notion of impartiality is free.
**** See Rawls 1973, p. 139.
∗ To give some flesh to this general statement, let us
examine more closely Harsanyi’s principle. In the first
step, a chooser of principle considers each possible
principle for cooperative action. Next, she calculates the
expected utility of a given principle’s adoption for each
The Concept of Justice from the Contractarian Perspective
284 Проблеми філософії права. – 2005. – Том III. – № 1-2.
Social an economic inequalities are to be arranged
so that they are both: (a) to the greatest benefit of the
least advantaged, consistent with the just savings
principle, and (b) attached to offices and positions
open to all under conditions of fair equality of oppor-
tunity∗∗.
According to Gauthier, however, neither Harsanyi
nor Rawls succeeded in providing a standpoint from
which the principle of justice rational for all parties to
the social contract might be chosen∗∗∗. Gauthier
claims that such a standpoint is gained if we interpret
the social contract as ICB. Gauthier offers a precise
definition of the social contract thus understood,
which we shall summarize below∗∗∗∗:
Let P be the set of all basic institutions and prac-
tices*****. Let N be any set of persons. For any N,
there will be a proper subset of P, P(N) including all
sets of basic social institutions and practices which are
possible for N. P(N) is therefore the set of possible
bases for societies, for the members of N. For each
person i in N, there will be a subset of P(N), Ai [P(N)]
which includes all sets of basic social institutions and
practices which it would be rational for her to accept
in order to enter society. The social contract for N, S
(N), will be the intersection of the sets Ai [P(N)] for
all i in N. Therefore, it is a set of sets of basic institu-
tions and practices which all members of N could ra-
tionally accept to enter society (of course S(N) may be
an empty set, which means that social cooperation is
not mutually advantageous for all members of N).
By definition, a bargain is rational provided it is
rational from everyone’s standpoint. Of course, in
order that the ICB approach to the idea of the social
contract be successful, there must exist a unique solu-
party to the contract. In the third step, she determines the
average of these expected utilities for each principle (this
step implies the usage of some interpersonally
comparable measure of utility). Finally, she selects the
principle that maximizes the average of the expected
utilities of the parties. We may remark en passant that it
is doubtful whether Harsanyi’s procedure is consistent
with the requirement that in the state of nature, no agent
can know her utility function. Besides, it is questionable
whether on can identify the expected utilities of different
persons with the average expected utility of a chooser; as
Rawls says, “the average of expected utilities is not, as
expectations should be, founded on one system of aims”
(Rawls, 1973, p. 175). See also Harsanyi 1976 and
Gauthier 1978, p. 51.
∗∗ Rawls 1973, p. 302.
∗∗∗ See point 8 (column for IID) of our table.
∗∗∗∗ See Gauthier 1978, p. 60.
***** That is, of “those procedures which allocate social
costs and distribute social benefits” - ibid., p. 60.
tion to the bargaining problem. This solution is the
content of the social contract. Gauthier’s proposal of
such a solution, i.e., his theory of justice, is the mini-
max relative concession principle. This principle re-
quires that each bargainer should receive the same
proportion of the difference between her status
quo****** and the maximum utility compatible with the
other obtaining their status quo payoffs, and that this
proportion should be maximal.
Ad.7. Considering that the IID approach in con-
trast with the ICB is based on the concept of moral
person, it should be clear that the interpretation of the
social contract as IID is assumed within the Kantian
tradition.
5. Final remarks
It was not our intention in this article to attempt to
declare either for the Kantian or for the Hobbesian
approach to the idea of the social contract. All we
wanted to achieve was to present these approaches in
a possibly comprehensive way, e.g., by showing their
correlation with two different models of the social
contract. We wanted to demonstrate that contractarian
theories help explicate the notion of justice, i.e., that they
reveal that justice can be understood either as mutual ad-
vantage or as impartiality. We hope to have demonstrated
that this most general distinction underlies and determines
the differences between specific principles of justice pro-
posed by different philosophers.
Reference
1. Atger F. (1906), Essai sur l’Histoire des
Doctrines du Contrat Social, Paris.
2. Axelrod R. (1984), The Evolution of Coopera-
tion, Basic Books, New York.
3. Buchanan J. (1975), The Limits of Liberty, The
University of Chicago Press, Chicago-London.
4. Dworkin R. (1978), The Original Position, in:
N. Daniels (1978), Reading Rawls. Critical Studies on
Rawls’ A Theory of Justice, Basic Blackwell, Oxford.
5. Gauthier D. (1978), The Social Contract: Individ-
ual Decision or Collective Bargain?. In C. A. Hooker,
J. J. Leach, E. F. McClennen (editors), Foundations
and Applications of Decision Theory, Vol. II, Reidel
Publishers, Dordrecht, 47-67 (1986), Morals by
Agreement, Clarendon Press, Oxford.
6. Hampton J. (2001),Two Faces of Contractarian
Thought. In: P. Vallentyne (ed.) (2001), Contractari-
anism and Rational Choice. Essays on David
Gauthier’s Morals by Agreement, Cambridge Univer-
****** Status quo determines payoffs bargainers would
receive were they to fail to reach the agreement.
W. Zaluski
Проблеми філософії права. – 2005. – Том III. – № 1-2. 285
sity Press, Cambridge, pp.31-55. (First published
1991) (2002), Umowa i zgoda, w: (R E. Goodin P.
Pettit (red.) (2002), Przewodnik po współczesnej filo-
zofii politycznej (A Companion to Contemporary Po-
litical Philosophy 1993), Książka i Wiedza, War-
szawa, 489-507.
7. Hargreaves Heap S. P., Varoufakis Y. (1996),
Game Theory. A Critical Introduction, Routledge,
London – New York.
8. Harsanyi J. C. (1976), Cardinal Welfare, Indi-
vidualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of
Utility. In: J C. Harsanyi (1976), Essays on Ethics,
Social Behavior, and Scientific Explanation, D. Rei-
del Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Boston p. 6-24.
(1977), Rational Behavior and Bargaining Equilib-
rium in Games and Social Situations, Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge-London- New York -
Melbourne.
9. Kymlicka W. (1998a), Tradycja umowy społec-
znej, w: Przewodnik po etyce (red. P.Singer) (A Com-
panion to Ethics1991), Książka i Wiedza, Warszawa,
s.226-237. (1998b),Współczesna filozofia polityczna,
(Contempoary Political Philosophy. An Introduction.
1990), przeł. A. Pawelec, Znak, Kraków.
10. Rawls J. (1973), A Theory of Justice, Harvard
University Press, Cambr., Mass.
11. Scanlon T. M. (1983), Contractualism and
Utilitarianism. In: A. Sen, B. Williams (ed.) (1983),
Utilitarianism and beyond, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge, pp.103-128.
12. Vallentyne P. (2001), Gauthier’s Three Pro-
jects. In: P. Vallentyne (ed.) (2001), Contractarianism
and Rational Choice. Essays on David Gauthier’s
Morals by Agreement, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, p.1-11 (First published 1991).
В. Залуски
КОНЦЕПЦИЯ СПРАВЕДЛИВОСТИ С ПОЗИЦИИ ТЕОРИЙ
ОБЩЕСТВЕННОГО ДОГОВОРА
Данная статья посвящена анализу научных подходов Канта и Гоббса к идее общественного дого-
вора и их влиянию на концепцию справедливости. В статье раскрыто взаимоотношение указанных
подходов с двумя разными моделями общественного договора. Показана роль теорий общественного
договора в процессе развития понятия справедливости. Автор указал, что относительно теорий обще-
ственного договора справедливость может рассматриваться или как взаимная выгода или как беспри-
страстность.
W. Załuski
THE CONCEPT OF JUSTICE FROM THE CONTRACTARIAN PERSPECTIVE
The present article is dedicated to the analysis of the Kantian and the Hobbesian approaches to the idea of the
social contract and their influence on the concept of justice. The correlation of these approaches with two
different models of the social contract has been shown. The role of the contractarian theories in the process
of explication of the notion of justice has been demonstrated. The author points out that according to the
contractarian theories justice can be realized either as the mutual advantage or as the impartiality.
|