Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications

A basis for a new relativity theory and a new physical concept are established. They lead to a further development of the theory of natural tracking control of nonlinear systems.

Gespeichert in:
Bibliographische Detailangaben
Datum:1999
1. Verfasser: Gruyitch, Ly. T.
Format: Artikel
Sprache:English
Veröffentlicht: Інститут математики НАН України 1999
Schriftenreihe:Нелінійні коливання
Online Zugang:http://dspace.nbuv.gov.ua/handle/123456789/177267
Tags: Tag hinzufügen
Keine Tags, Fügen Sie den ersten Tag hinzu!
Назва журналу:Digital Library of Periodicals of National Academy of Sciences of Ukraine
Zitieren:Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications / Ly. T. Gruyitch // Нелінійні коливання. — 1999. — Т. 2, № 4. — С. 465-489. — Бібліогр.: 80 назв. — англ.

Institution

Digital Library of Periodicals of National Academy of Sciences of Ukraine
id irk-123456789-177267
record_format dspace
spelling irk-123456789-1772672021-02-16T01:25:31Z Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications Gruyitch, Ly. T. A basis for a new relativity theory and a new physical concept are established. They lead to a further development of the theory of natural tracking control of nonlinear systems. Встановлено концепцiю нової теорiї вiдносностi та нових фiзичних принципiв. Це зумовлює подальший розвиток адекватної теорiї керування нелiнiйними системами. 1999 Article Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications / Ly. T. Gruyitch // Нелінійні коливання. — 1999. — Т. 2, № 4. — С. 465-489. — Бібліогр.: 80 назв. — англ. 1562-3076 http://dspace.nbuv.gov.ua/handle/123456789/177267 531/534.01 en Нелінійні коливання Інститут математики НАН України
institution Digital Library of Periodicals of National Academy of Sciences of Ukraine
collection DSpace DC
language English
description A basis for a new relativity theory and a new physical concept are established. They lead to a further development of the theory of natural tracking control of nonlinear systems.
format Article
author Gruyitch, Ly. T.
spellingShingle Gruyitch, Ly. T.
Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications
Нелінійні коливання
author_facet Gruyitch, Ly. T.
author_sort Gruyitch, Ly. T.
title Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications
title_short Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications
title_full Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications
title_fullStr Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications
title_full_unstemmed Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications
title_sort time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications
publisher Інститут математики НАН України
publishDate 1999
url http://dspace.nbuv.gov.ua/handle/123456789/177267
citation_txt Time, relativity and physical principle: generalizations and applications / Ly. T. Gruyitch // Нелінійні коливання. — 1999. — Т. 2, № 4. — С. 465-489. — Бібліогр.: 80 назв. — англ.
series Нелінійні коливання
work_keys_str_mv AT gruyitchlyt timerelativityandphysicalprinciplegeneralizationsandapplications
first_indexed 2025-07-15T15:18:26Z
last_indexed 2025-07-15T15:18:26Z
_version_ 1837726651184578560
fulltext т. 2 •№ 4 • 1999 UDC 531 / 534 . 01 TIME, RELATIVITY AND PHYSICAL PRINCIPLE : GENERALIZATIONS AND APPLICATIONS ЧАС, ВIДНОСНIСТЬ I ФIЗИЧНI ПРИНЦИПИ : УЗАГАЛЬНЕННЯ I ЗАСТОСУВАННЯ Ly. T. Gruyitch Univ. Technology Belfort-Montbeliard, Site de Belfort, Thierry Mieg, 90010 Belfort Cedex, France A basis for a new relativity theory and a new physical concept are established. They lead to a further development of the theory of natural tracking control of nonlinear systems. Встановлено концепцiю нової теорiї вiдносностi та нових фiзичних принципiв. Це зумовлює подальший розвиток адекватної теорiї керування нелiнiйними системами. 1. Introduction. Different physical sub-processes of a complex physical process can have di- fferent natural speeds of their evolutions. This inspired a study of processes and systems with multiple time scales [1 – 7]. Such examples are different speeds of fluidic, electrical, mechani- cal and thermal processes in chemical industry, process industry, and in power stations. Other examples are in control systems, in econometric systems, in biological systems. The fact that a change of a time scale influences the (numerical) value of the speed, and the fact that different natural velocities of evolutions of different processes can justify different time scales, have been well exploited to simplify the analysis of various dynamical system properties. The analysis is simplified by reducing their analysis to that of separated subprocesses or subsystems as well as to a study of their interactions, which appeared effective in particular in the framework of large scale dynamical systems [8]. The importance of a change of a time scale was well recognised and emphasised by Newton [9], who introduced and explained the meaning and defined the sense not only of the absolute time but also of the relative time that has been very rarely referred to in the literature on time. The meaning and sense of time has been an intrinsic topic at least from Heraclit’s epoch [10] and were considered from purely mathematical and systems point of view [11, 12], from physical points of view [10, 13 – 27] or from a philosophical standpoint [28 – 34]. Historical reviews can be found in [35, 36]. Using the Lorentz transformation of both time and space coordinates [37 – 41], which ori- ginated from a paper by Voigt as confirmed by Lorentz himself [40] and which was efficiently applied at the early development of the relativity theory by Poincaré [42], Einstein introduced and established another, different from Newton’s, meaning and sense of the time relativity [43 – 47]. The modern literature on time has accepted Einstein’s explication of time [10, 13 – 27] as the basic point of the relativity theory nevertheless whether it is treated purely mathematically c© Ly. T. Gruyitch, 1999 465 [41, 48 – 51] or also from a physical point of view [47, 48, 50, 52 – 62]. Another crucial point of the relativity theory is the postulate on the constancy of the velocity of light in vacuum relative to inertial frames, which has been interpreted as and used for invariance of its value relative to a change of a time scale [43 – 47, 63, 64]. Analysing all this the following questions have been risen: Q1. Is time a physical or purely mathematical variable, or even only a mathematical para- meter? Q2. Is there an explanation and definition of time that can incorporate both Newton’s and Einstein’s? Q3. How does a change of a time scale influence the light speed value and should not be a time scale accepted before a light speed value is considered? Q4. What is an influence of a change of a time scale on Lorentz transformation via its influence on the light speed value? Q5. Is it possible to generalize the Lorentz transformation by obeying Einstein’s conditions imposed on the transformation for its validity? Since all these questions have been recently affirmatively replied by showing that the Lorentz transformation is just a singular case [65, 66], then they cause other questions to be posed, replied and explained: Q6. How the generalized Lorentz transformation from the references [65, 66] can be used further in physics, what are its implications on: a) velocity; b) acceleration; c) mass; d) force; e) energy, and whether essentially new relationships result? Q7. What are implications on the relativity theory, does the generalized Lorentz transformation lead to new views on the relativity theory, does it constitute a basis for a generalization of the relativity theory? Q8. Does the meaning, sense and definition of time accepted in [65, 66] provide another opening important for physics and possibly for other scientific and/or engineering theories and/or applications? For the sake of the continuity and causality of the presentation and due to the delicacy and importance of replies to the posed questions the paper will present solutions to the first five questions by referring to [65, 66] where the proofs can be found. They enable us to reply to all other questions and to prove rigorously the statements, which is the primary goal of the paper. The results provide complete affirmative replies and explanations, and open various new avenues of research and development in physics, mathematics, systems and control (science and engineering). They also offer a new basis for philosophical understanding and interpretation of time. They also explain why every person has a feeling of her/his own time. The accepted definition of time discovers no collision with Newton’s meaning of the time relativity and simultaneously leads to new results in the relativity theory generalizing those by Lorentz [37 – 40] and Einstein [43 – 46], which therefore follow as special cases. Furthermore, the properties of time clearly explained in and reflected by the accepted defi- nition lead to a new physical principle to be stated, which appears in particular useful for development of novel directions in control science and engineering that will be also shown. 466 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 2. Physical variables and time. Accepted meanings of basic notions will be explained for the sake of preciseness and clearness of the presentation. A quantity that can change its value is a variable. A variable is a physical variable if and only if there is a material object such that its (complete or partial) instantaneous internal (physical) situation at any its point is expressed by an instantaneous value of the variable at the same point and at the same moment. A physical variable can take any value from a set of its values, which is infinite and everywhere dense. Time is an independent physical variable the value of which is strictly monotonously conti- nuously increasing independently of all other (physical and mathematical) variables, processes and events, which is used to uniquely determine the order of events happening. The value of time is called moment or instant and is denoted by t or by τ and a subscript, e.g. t2 or τb. An arbitrary instant will be denoted as time itself by t or by τ . The time value is determined accurately up to an unknown additive constant, that is that we do not know what is total zero time value: t = 0. We accept it conventionally like for some other variables (e.g. position, voltage). Moment (instant) reflects an instantaneous internal physical situation of a material object called its age. Time value difference (time interval) is used to measure duration of a process, of a movement or of a rest. Different materials can have different speeds of ageing, which can hold also for the same material object at its different points. For this reason, different time scales (e.g. decimal, logari- thmic), different initial moments and / or different time units (e.g. second, minute) can be assig- ned to different material objects and / or to different parts of the same material object giving a relative meaning to time in this sense. This is Newtonian meaning of the relativity of time. It should be noted that Newton [9, p. 8 – 10] introduced and determined not only the absolute but also a relative sense of time. Einstein accepted another relative sense of time [43, p. 20; 45, p. 26 – 27; 46, p. 23 – 40]. With the above Newtonian relative sense of time in mind it is clear why different persons think that time has different speeds for them; i.e. that each of them has its own personal time. In fact, they think of the personal velocities of their processes. For example, if a discussion was interesting then its process went “fast” and a person usually say “time passed fast during the discussion”, or if a discussion was uninteresting then the person would say “time passed slow”, although in both cases the discussions could really last equally. Since time value is strictly monotonously continuously increasing then dt > 0 is only meaningful. Time is indispensable for the definition and measurement of the speed (accelerati- on,...) of a value change of every variable. The speed value is measured relative to an accepted time scale. The former is possible only after having defined the latter, which means that we cannot determine a speed value if a time scale and unite have not been well defined. A path (vector) dr passed by a light array over an infinitesimal time interval dt is the light speed (vector) c(t) = dr(t) dt at moment t. The value of the light speed c(t) = ‖c(t)‖ is constant in vacuum: c(t) = c [43, p. 15; 45, p. 26], which is the light speed relative to the vacuum, for short: the light speed. In what follows, the environment will be arbitrary but fixed and such that it enables a constant light speed. The environment dimension n ∈ {1, 2, . . .}. We consider it as an n-dimensional real vector space and denote it by Rn. A fixed point O can be accepted in the environment Rn to be the origin of a system of reference (a coordinate system). We can accept another point OA movable relative to the environment to be the origin of another coordinate system denoted byRnA. The speed v0A(t) of the pointOA and of the reference system ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 467 RnA relative to the environment Rn is accepted constant: v0A(t) = v0A = ν0Ar0, where ν0A = ‖v0A‖ is the Euclidean norm of v0A and r0 is a unity vector, ‖r0‖ = 1. A coordinate axis used for a time axis that is immovable relative to the environment is denoted by T . It is a set of all instants: T = {t : t ∈ R, t ∈ C(1)(R), dt > 0}. Once a time axis has been accepted with a fixed time scale including a fixed time interval unit, then the zero time should have been also accepted. Any instant τ0 ∈ T can be accepted for an initial instant. We accept that it has been chosen and fixed. It can be τ0 = 0. The Cartesian product set T × Rn is denoted by J , J = T × Rn. It is called the (n + 1)- dimensional real integral space, for short the integral space. It enables a complete presentation of motions (of solutions of differential equations from a mathematical point of view, which are called integral trajectories). A pair (t, x) is called an event in J [11]. It can happen only once. 3. Physical continuity and uniqueness principle [67 – 70]. A physical variable value depends at least on both time and spatial coordinates of a point at which its value is considered. Such a dependence is uniquely determined. If the point is fixed then the physical variable can change its value only continuously in terms of time. These are real features of physical variables, which are expressed by the physical continuity and uniqueness principle. Physical Continuity and Uniqueness Principle (PCUP): a) Physical Continuity Principle: A physical variable can change its value from one value to another one only by passing through all intermediate values. b) Physical Uniqueness Principle: A physical variable possesses a unique local instantaneous real value at any place (in any being or in any object) at any moment. The continuity of time is crucial for applications of the Physical Continuity and Uniqueness Principle. It will be explained by analysing mathematical and physical responses of various nonlinear functions (nonlinearities) y(·) : R→ R, Fig. 1 through Fig. 5. Fig. 1. A block representing a nonlinearity y(·). The Physical Continuity and Uniqueness Principle enables us to explain how the Nature and beings exploit time continuity to create control. The Principle will be used in the sequel to explain and synthesise such a control of technical objects, which is called natural (tracking) control [71 – 80]. 468 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 Fig. 2. Discontinuous nonlinearity y(·). It is double valued at x = a. Fig. 3. Discontinuous nonlinearity y(·). It is single valued at x = a. Fig. 4. Discontinuous nonlinearity y(·). It is multi-valued at x = a. ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 469 Fig. 5. Continuous nonlinearity y(·). It is single valued at x = a. 4. Time, speed and coordinate transformation [66]. What is presented in this section is from [66] (except the Corollary 1) and represents the basis for new results established in the next sections. 4.1. Time scale and speed. A time scale of a time axis T can be variously accepted. Let three different time scales be associated with T : “an original time scale” that is not indexed, “a”-time scale and “b”-time scale, which are then denoted respectively by T , Ta and Tb. A time value (instant) measured in T -scale, Ta-scale and Tb-scale is designated by τ , τa and τb, respectively, τ ∈ T , τa ∈ Ta and τb ∈ Tb. We accept τ0 = µ−1 a τa0 = µ−1 b τb0 ∈ T and fix them in the sequel. Time scale factors µa and µb are positive numbers. Immovable time axes (such as T , Ta and Tb) are only considered in the what follows. Integral spaces corresponding to the time axes T , Ta and Tb are J , Ja and Jb, respectively: J = T ×R , Ja = Ta ×Rna and Jb = Tb ×Rnb . Let the origin Oa of Rna and Ob of Rnb move with constant vOa and vOb relative to the origin O of Rn. This means that the integral space Ja (Jb) is movable relative to the integral space J in the above sense that Oa and Rna (i.e. Ob and Rnb ) are only movable, but not the time axes Ta and Tb. Norms of the speeds vOa and vOb are denoted by vOa and vOb , when measured relative to t ∈ T . Since the light propagates equally in all directions then we can accept to consider a light signal and translations of Oa together with Rna and of Ob together with Rnb in a direction and sense of an arbitrary unity vector r0 ∈ Rn that is also used to represent symbolically the spaces Rn, Rna and Rnb in Fig. 6. Analogously, without losing in generality, we represent arbitrary elementwise constant vectors r ∈ Rn, ra ∈ Rna and rb ∈ Rnb as r = ρr0, ra = ρar0 and rb = ρbr0. Their lengths expressed by their norms ρ = ‖r‖, ρa = ‖ra‖ and ρb = ‖rb‖, respectively, do not depend on a time scale used. Velocities should be naturally permitted to depend on a time scale used: vOa(τa) ≡ vaOa ≡ vaOar0 — speed of Oa relative to O at an instant τa measured in terms of τa, vaOa ≤ vaOb is accepted, vOb(τb) ≡ vbOb ≡ v b Ob r0 — speed of Ob relative to O at an instant τb measured in terms of τb, vbOa ≤ v b Ob is accepted, ν(τa) ≡ νa ≡ νar0 ≡ (vaOb − v a Oa )r0 — relative speed of Ob with respect to Oa at instant τa measured all in terms of τa; it is to be noted that νa 6= −ca due to the accepted vaOa ≤ v a Ob , 470 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 Fig. 6. Movable origins Oa of Rna and Ob of Rnb , as well as Rna and Rnb themselves relative to the origin O of Rn and relative to Rn itself. The time axes T , Ta and Tb are immovable. c — the value of the light speed measured relative to τ ∈ T , ca — the value of the light speed measured relative to τa ∈ Ta, ν(τb) ≡ νb ≡ νbr0 ≡ (vbOb − v b Oa )r0 — relative speed of Ob with respect to Oa at instant τb measured all in terms of τb; it is accepted that νb 6= cb, cb — the value of the light speed measured relative to τb ∈ Tb. 4.2. Problem statement. What are values of the coefficients kba and kab , αba and αab such that the equations (1), ra(τa; τa0) = kab [ rb(τb; τb0)− νb(τb − τb0)r0 ] , (1a) rb(τb; τb0) = kba [ ra(τa; τa0) + νa(τa − τa0)r0 ] , (1b) and the equations (2), τa − τa0 = αab [ (τb − τb0)− νb (cb)2 ρb(τb; τb0) ] , (2a) τb − τb0 = αba [ (τa − τa0) + νa (ca)2 ρa(τa; τa0) ] , (2b) hold and that they imply both the equations (3), τa − τa0 = µa(t− t0) , µa ∈ R+ =]0,∞[ , (3a) τb − τb0 = µb(t− t0) , µb ∈ R+ , (3b) and the equation (4), r2 a(τa; τa0)− [ ca(τa − τa0) ]2 = r2 b (τb; τb0)− [ cb(τb − τb0) ]2 (4) and what are values of the factors µa and µb? ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 471 The time-scale equations (3) are inherent for multiple time scale systems. The condition (4) is a crucial condition of the Einstein relativity theory for validity of the coordinate transformati- on defined by (1) and (2) [43, 44]. 4.3. Problem solution. Let a light signal be emitted from O = Oa0 = Ob0 at an initial instant τ0 = µ−1 a τa0 = µ−1 b τb0. Let its position be determined by r(τ ; τ0) in Rn at an instant τ ; by ra(τa; τa0) in Rna at τa and by rb(τb; τb0) in Rnb at τb. Hence: r (τ ; τ0) = c (τ − τ0) r0 = r (τ − τ0; 0) , (5a) ra (τa; τa0) = ca (τa − τa0) rv = ra (τa − τa0; 0) , (5b) and rb (τb; τb0) = cb (τb − τb0) r0 = rb (τb − τb0; 0) . (5c) The distance vectors can be expressed also in terms of their lengths (norms), r (τ ; τ0) = ρ (τ − τ0) r0 , (6a) ra (τa; τa0) = ρa (τa − τa0) r0 , (6b) and rb (τb; τb0) = ρb (τb − τb0) r0 . (6c) Two cases should be distinguished and will be considered: General case: kba 6= kab and / or αba 6= αab . All the coefficients kba, kab , αba and αab ∈ R+ =]0,∞[. Special case: kba = kab = k ∈ R+ and αba = αab = α ∈ R+. Problem solution for the general case. Theorem 1. In order for the coefficients kba ∈ R+, kab ∈ R+, kba 6= kab , αba ∈ R+ and αab ∈ R+, αba 6= αab , to obey (1) and (2), and for (1) and (2) to imply (3) and (4) it is necessary and sufficient that the following equations hold for any choice of µa ∈ R+: αab = 1 1− νb cb µa µb = cb ca kab , (7a) αba = 1 1 + νa ca µb µa = ca cb kba , (7b) νb < cb , (7c) kba = 1 1 + νa ca , (8a) kab = 1 1− νb cb , (8b) 472 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 and µb = ca cb µa . (9) Proof. It is given in Appendix A of [66]. The equations (7) and (8) give the next form to the equations (1) and (2): ra(τa; τa0) = [ rb(τb; τb0)− νb(τb − τb0)r0 ] 1− νb cb , (1a′) rb(τb; τb0) = [ra(τa; τa0)− νa(τa − τa0)r0] 1 + νa ca , (1b′) τa − τa0 = cb ca 1 1− νb cb [ (τb − τb0)− νb (cb)2 ρb(τb; τb0) ] , (2a′) τb − τb0 = ca cb 1 1 + νa ca [ (τa − τa0) + νa (ca)2 ρa(τa; τa0) ] . (2b′) The definition of the speed, and the equations (3) and (9) verify directly the follo- wing known relationship among time scales and velocity scales, which are linked with the corresponding light speed values. Corollary 1. Let va = var0 = v(τa; τa0) r0 and vb = vbr0 = v(τb; τb0) r0 be the velocities of the same point in the same space coordinate system Rn but relative to time measured in two different time scales Ta and Tb. Let the corresponding values of the light speed be ca = car0 = c(τa; τa0)r0 and cb = cbr0 = c(τb; τb0)r0, respectively. Then: va vb = µb µa = ca cb . In the case the coordinate systems Rna and Rnb move with the same velocities then the next theorem is easily proved by setting νa = νb = 0 in the proof of Theorem 1 (Appendix A in [66]): Theorem 2. Let the coordinate systemsRna andRnb move with the same velocities. In order for the coefficients kba ∈ R+, kab ∈ R+, αba ∈ R+ and αab ∈ R+, αba 6= αab , to obey (1) and (2), and for (1) and (2) to imply (3) and (4) it is necessary and sufficient that the following equations hold for any choice of µa ∈ R+: αab = µa µb = cb ca , αba = µb µa = ca cb = (αab ) −1 , and kba = kab = 1 . This result shows that different time scales can be chosen in the case αba 6= αab even the co- ordinate systems Rna and Rnb move with the same velocities. This is a consequence of the time independence of the space. Then the time scale coefficients are related to the corresponding values of the light speed by the equation (9). Hence, it is still possible to model dynamic systems ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 473 with multiple time scales by applying the coordinate transformation defined by (1) and (2) or equivalently by (1′) and (2′). Problem solution for the special case. Theorem 3. In order for the coefficients kba ∈ R+, kab ∈ R+, kba = kab = k, αba ∈ R+ and αab ∈ R+, αba = αab = α, to obey (1) and (2), and for (1) and (2) to imply (3) and (4) it is necessary and sufficient that the following equations hold for any choice of µa ∈ R+: ca = cb = c , (10) νa = νb = ν , (11) α = k = 1√ 1− ν2 c2 , (12) µb = µa √√√√√1 + ν c 1− ν c . (13) Proof. It is shown in Appendix B of [66]. The preceding theorem gives the following special form to the equations (1): r (τa; τa0) = [r(τb; τb0)− ν(τb − τb0) r0]√ 1− ν2 c2 , (14a) r (τb; τb0) = [r(τa; τa0) + ν(τa − τa0) r0]√ 1− ν2 c2 , (14b) and to the equations (2), τa − τa0 = (τb − τb0)− ν c2 ρb(τb; τb0)√ 1− ν2 c2 , (15a) τb − τb0 = (τa − τa0) + ν c2 ρa(τa; τa0)√ 1− ν2 c2 . (15b) These equations are well known as the equations of the Lorentz transformation [37 – 41, 51]. They are basic for the Einstein theory of relativity [43 – 46]. It is now clear that they appear a singular case of the transformations (1) and (2). It should be also noted that they follow herein from the accepted time definition in Newton’s sense. If the reference systems Rna and Rnb move with the same speed then the preceding theorem reduces to: 474 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 Corollary 2. Let the coordinate systems Rna and Rnb move with the same velocities. In order for the coefficients kba ∈ R+, kab ∈ R+, kba = kab = k, αba ∈ R+ and αab ∈ R+, αba = αab = α, to obey (1) and (2), and for (1) and (2) to imply (3) and (4) it is necessary and sufficient that the following equations hold for any choice of µa ∈ R+: ca = cb = c , α = k = 1 , µb = µa . (16) An illustrative example is worked out in [66]. 5. Dynamical variables and coordinate transformation. In this and next sections new relati- onships will be derived by employing the generalized Lorentz transformation (1′), (2′) and the results obtained in [65, 66] that are presented in the preceding section. 5.1. Speed and coordinate transformation. The general case. Theorem 4. Let the coefficients kba ∈ R+, kab ∈ R+, kba 6= kab , αba ∈ R+ and αab ∈ R+, αba 6= αab , obey (1) and (2), and let (1) and (2) imply (3) and (4). Then the speed vOAA (τa; τa0) of a point A relative to the origin OA of Ra expressed as a function of τa and the speed vOBA (τb; τb0) of the point A relative to the origin OB of Rb expressed as a function of τb are interrelated as follows: vOAA (τa; τa0) = ca cb vOBA (τb; τb0)− νb 1− νbvOBA (τb; τb0) (cb)2 r0 , (17a) and vOBA (τb; τb0) = cb ca vOAA (τa; τa0) + νa 1 + νavOAA (τa; τa0) (ca)2 r0 . (17b) Proof. Let all the conditions of the theorem statement hold. Then, the equations (1′) and (2′) also hold (Theorem 1). The speed vOAA (ta) is defined by: vOAA (τa; τa0) = drOAA (τa; τa0) dτa . This equation, and the equations (1′) and (2′) now yield: vOAA (τa; τa0) = drOAA (τa; τa0) dτa = = d[rOBA (τb; τb0)− νb(τb − τbo)r0] 1− νb/cb d { cb ca 1 1− νb/cb [ (τb − τb0)− νb (cb)2 ρOBA (τb; τb0) ]} = ca cb vOBA (τb; τb0)− νbr0 1− νb (cb)2 vOBA (τb; τb0) , which proves (17a). The equation (17b) is analogously proved by starting with the definition of vOBA (τb; τb0), vOBA (τb; τb0) = drOBA (τb; τb0) dτb , (18) and by using (1b′) and (2b′). ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 475 The velocity transformation equations (17) are beyond those of the relativity theory. The former are general, while the latter result from the special case. Notice once more that νa = = νb = ν and ca = cb = c in the special case. The special case. Theorem 5. Let the coefficients kba ∈ R+, kab ∈ R+, kba = kab = k, αba ∈ R+ and αab ∈ R+, αba = αab = α, obey (1) and (2), and let (1) and (2) imply (3) and (4). Then the speed vOAA (τa; τa0) of a pointA relative to the originOA ofRa expressed as a function of τa and the speed vOBA (τb; τb0) of the point A relative to the origin OB of Rb expressed as a function of τb are interrelated as follows: vOAA (τa; τa0) = vOBA (τb; τb0)− ν 1− νvOBA (τb; τb0) c2 r0 , (19a) and vOBA (τb; τb0) = vOAA (τa; τa0) + ν 1 + νvOAA (τa; τa0) c2 r0 . (19b) Proof. Let all the conditions of the theorem statement hold. Then, the equations (14) and (15) also hold (Theorem 3). The speed vOAA is determined by the equations (14a) and (15a) as follows: vOAA (τa; τa0) drOAA (τa; τa0) dτa = = d[rOBA (τb; τb0)− ν(τb − τbo)r0]√ 1− ν2/c2 d [ (τb − τb0)− ν c2 ρb(τb; τb0) ] √ 1− ν2/c2 : dτb dτb = vOBA (τb; τb0)− νr0 1− ν c2 vOBA (τb; τb0) , which implies (19a). The equation (19b) is analogously proved by starting with the definition of vOBA (τb; τb0), (18), and by using (14b) and (15b). Notice that the equations (19) can be also derived directly from the equations (17) for ca = = cb = c due to Corollary 1 and the conditions of Theorem 5. The equations (19) are well known in the relativity theory. It is important to note that they are derived herein starting with the time definition in Newton’s sense rather than in Einstein’s. 5.2. Acceleration and coordinate transformation. The general case. Theorem 6. Let the coefficients kba ∈ R+, kab ∈ R+, kba 6= kab , αba ∈ R+ and αab ∈ R+, αba 6= αab , obey (1) and (2), and let (1) and (2) imply (3) and (4). Then the acceleration aOAA (τa; τa0) of a po- intA relative to the originOA ofRa expressed as a function of τa and the acceleration aOBA (τb; τb0) of the point A relative to the origin OB of Rb expressed as a function of τb are interrelated as follows: aOAA (τa; τa0) = ( ca cb )2( 1 + νb cb ) ( 1− νb cb )2 [ 1− νbvOBA (τb; τb0) (cb)2 ]3 aOBA (τb; τb0) , (20a) 476 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 and aOBA (τb; τb0) = ( cb ca )2( 1− νa ca ) ( 1 + νa ca )2 [ 1 + νavOBA (τa; τa0) (cb)2 ]3 aOAA (τa; τa0) . (20b) Proof. Let all the conditions of the theorem statement hold. Then, the equations (2′) and (17) also hold (Theorem 1 and Theorem 4). The acceleration aOAA (τa; τa0) is defined by: aOAA (τa; τa0) = dvOAA (τa; τa0) dτa . This equation, the equations (17a) and (2a′) now yield: aOAA (τa; τa0) = = d [ ca cb vOBA (τb; τb0)− νbr0 1− νbvOBA (τb; τb0) (cb)2 ] d  cb ca 1 1− νb cb [ (τb − τb0)− νb (cb)2 ρOBA (τb; τb0) ] : dτb dτb = ( 1− νb cb ) ( ca cb )2 × × [ dvOBA (τb; τb0) dτb ][ 1− νbvOBA (τb; τb0) (cb)2 ] − [ vOBA (τb; τb0)− νb ] [ − νb (cb)2 dvOBA (τb; τb0) dτb ] [ 1− νbvOBA (τb; τb0) (cb)2 ]2{[ 1− νb (cb)2 dρOBA (τb; τb0) dτb ]} r0 = = ( ca cb )2( 1− νb cb ) 1− ( νb cb )2 [ 1− νbvOBA (τb; τb0) (cb)2 ]3 aOBA (τb; τb0) = = ( ca cb )2( 1 + νb cb ) ( 1− νb cb )2 [ 1− νbvOBA (τb; τb0) (cb)2 ]3 aOBA (τb; τb0), ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 477 which proves (20a). The equation (20b) is analogously proved by starting with the definition of aOBA (τb; τb0), aOBA (τb; τb0) = dvOBA (τb; τb0) dτb , (21) and by using (17b) and (2b′). The acceleration transformation equations (20) are beyond those of the relativity theory, The former are general, while the latter result from the special case as shown in what follows. The special case. Theorem 7. Let the coefficients kba ∈ R+, kab ∈ R+, kba = kab = k, αba ∈ R+ and αab ∈ R+, αba = αab = α, obey (1) and (2), and let (1) and (2) imply (3) and (4). Then the acceleration aOAA (τa; τa0) of a point A relative to the origin OA of Ra expressed as a function of τa and the acceleration aOBA (τb; τb0) of the point A relative to the origin OB of Rb expressed as a function of τb are interrelated as follows: aOAA (τa; τa0) = [ 1− (ν c )2 ]3/2 aOBA (τb; τb0)[ 1− νvOBA (τb; τb0) c2 ]3 , (22a) and aOBA (τb; τb0) = [ 1− (ν c )2 ]3/2 aOAA (τa; τa0)[ 1− νvOAA (τa; τa0) c2 ]3 . (22b) Proof. Let all the conditions of the theorem statement hold. Then, the equations (19) also hold (Theorem 5). The acceleration aOAA (τa; τa0) is determined by the equations (19a) and (15a) as follows: aOAA (τa; τa0) = dvOAA (τa; τa0) dτa = = d vOBA (τb; τb0)− νr0 1− νvOBA (τb; τb0) c2    d [ (τb − τb0)− νρOBA (τb; τb0) c2 ] √ 1− ν2 c2  −1 : dτb dτb = = √ 1− ν2 c2 aOBA (τb; τb0)− aOBA (τb; τb0) νvOBA (τb; τb0) c2 − [ vOBA (τb; τb0)− νr0 ] [ − νaOBA (τb; τb0) c2 ] [ 1− νvOBA (τb; τb0) c2 ]2 [ 1− νvOBA (τb; τb0) c2 ] . 478 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 This can be set in the next form: aOAA (τa; τa0) = √ 1− ν2 c2 ( 1− ν2 c2 ) aOBA (τb; τb0)[ 1− νvOBA (τb; τb0) c2 ]3 , or aOAA (τa; τa0) = ( 1− ν2 c2 )3/2 aOBA (τb; τb0)[ 1− νvOBA (τb; τb0) c2 ]3 , which implies (22a). The equation (22b) is analogously proved by starting with the definition of aOBA (τb; τb0), (21), and by using (15b) and (19b). Notice that the equations (22) cannot be derived directly from the equations (20) for ca = = cb = c. The equations (22) are well known in the relativity theory. They are derived herein by starting with the time definition in Newton’s sense. 6. Mass and coordinate transformation. Let the example of two particles of equal masses at the rest considered by D’Inverno [52, p.45 – 47] be reconsidered, Fig. 7. They are assumed to collide inelastically. The reference frames R = Rn and RA = Rna : The reference frames R = Rn and RB = Rnb : Fig. 7. Two equal mass particles before and after the collision in the reference frames R, RA and RB : Ua = U(τa; τa0), U b = U(τb; τb0) = cb caU a (Corollary1), vOB1 = vOB1 (τb; τb0) = vOB1 r0. The three inertial coordinate systems (reference frames) are accepted. The coordinate system R = Rn is the reference coordinate system for other two coordinate systems RA = Rna and RB = Rnb , Fig. 7. The frame Rna is the “centre-of-mass” frame. Both particles move relative to the frame Rna . Their velocities have the same absolute value Ua measured in time scale Ta and before the collision, but opposite sence. Their common speed after the collision equals zero relative to the reference frame Rna . ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 479 The reference frame Rnb is tied with the particle 2. The second particle 2 is evidently at the rest also relative to Rnb , and both are at the rest relative to Rn by accepting that the frame Rnb does not move relative to Rn. Both particles move evidently with the common speed Ua with respect to the frame Rn after the collision, when the speed is measured relative to Ta. Their common speed value is U b with respect to the frame Rn after the collision if the speed is measured relative to Tb, and then Corollary 1 provides the following relationship (Fig. 7): Ua Ub = µa µb = ca cb . (23) The general case. Theorem 8. Let two identical particles 1 and 2 have the same mass m0 at the rest relative to a reference coordinate system T × Rn. Let another two coordinate systems Ta × Rna and Tb × Rnb be accepted, Ta 6= Tb. Let the space coordinate system Rna be the “centre-of-mass” frame. Let the space coordinate system Rnb be at the rest relative to Rn. Then, the mass m(vOB1 ) of the particle 1 moving with the speed vOB1 = vOB1 r0 = vOB1 (τb; τb0)r0 is related to its mass m0 at the rest relative to Rnb by m(vOB1 ) = m0√√√√1− ( vOB1 cb )2 . (24) Proof. Let all the conditions of the theorem statement hold. Then the law of the mass conservation and the law of the linear momentum take the following forms for the two particles: m(vOB1 ) +m0 = M(U b), m(vOB1 )vOB1 +m0 = M(U b)U b. These equations determine m(vOB1 ), after eliminating M(U b), as follows: m(vOB1 ) = U b vOB1 − U b m0. Combining the preceding equation with (23) we can express m(vOB1 ) in terms of Ua: m(vOB1 ) = cb ca Ua vOB1 − cb ca Ua m0, (25) which is suitable because we can determine Ua as follows by using (17b) in which vOAA (τa; τa0) = = vOA1 (τa; τa0) = Ua and νa = Ua: vOB1 = cb ca 2Ua 1 + ( Ua ca )2 . 480 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 This is to be solved for Ua: Ua = cacb vOB1 1± √√√√1− ( vOB1 cb )2  . From the condition that |Ua| <∞ should be satisfied as vOB1 → 0 we conclude that the negative sigh should be retained: Ua = cacb vOB1 1− √√√√1− ( vOB1 cb )2  . Replacing Ua by the right-hand side of this equation in the equation (25), and after simple algebraic manipulations we derive: m(vOB1 ) = m0√√√√1− ( vOB1 cb )2 , which proves (24). This generalizes the expression for the relativistic mass that exists in the relativity theory and which can be determined now easily for the special case. The special case. Theorem 9. Let two identical particles 1 and 2 have the same mass m0 at the rest relative to a reference coordinate system T × Rn. Let another two coordinate systems Ta × Rna and Tb × Rnb be accepted so that Ta = Tb. Let the space coordinate system Rna be the “centre-of-mass” frame. Let the space coordinate system Rnb be at the rest relative to Rn. Then, the mass m(vOB1 ) of the particle 1 moving with the speed vOB1 = vOB1 r0 = vOB1 (τb; τb0)r0 is related to its mass m0 at the rest relative to Rnb by m(vOB1 ) = m0√√√√1− ( vOB1 c )2 . (26) Proof. Let all the conditions of the theorem statement hold. Since T a = T b then by the definition µa = µb (the equations (3)) which together with (23) implies ca = cb = c. By replacing now cb by c in (24) we obtain (26) that is well known expression for the relativistic mass in the relativity theory. The equations (24) and (26) have been derived by starting with the time definition in Newton’s sense. 7. Force and coordinate transformation. The general case. Theorem 10. Let m0 be the mass of a particle 1 at the rest relative to a reference coordinate system T × Rn. Let another two coordinate systems Ta × Rna and Tb × Rnb be accepted, Ta 6= Tb. Let the space coordinate systemRna be the “centre-of-mass” frame for the particle 1 and a particle ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 481 2. Let the particle 2 be at the rest relative toRnb and let its mass be alsom0 at the rest. Let the space coordinate system Rnb be at the rest relative to Rn. Then, a force F acting on the particle 1, its speed vOB1 = vOB1 (τb; τb0)r0 and acceleration aOB1 = aOB1 (τb; τb0)r0 relative to Rnb are interrelated by: F(vOB1 ) = m01− ( vOB1 cb )2 3/2 aOB1 . (27) Proof. The equation (27) follows directly from Newton’s law: F(vOB1 ) = d dτb [ m(vOB1 ) vOB1 ] and (24). The special case. Theorem 11. Let m0 be the mass of a particle 1 at the rest relative to a reference coordinate system T × Rn. Let another two coordinate systems Ta × Rna and Tb × Rnb be accepted so that Ta = Tb. Let the space coordinate system Rna be the “centre-of-mass” frame for the particle 1 and a particle 2. Let the particle 2 be at the rest relative to Rnb ant its mass be also m0 at the rest. Let the space coordinate system Rnb be at the rest relative to Rn. Then, a force F acting on the particle 1, its speed vOB1 = vOB1 (τb; τb0)r0 and acceleration aOB1 = aOB1 (τb; τb0)r0 relative to Rnb are interrelated by: F(vOB1 ) = m01− ( vOB1 c )2 3/2 aOB1 . (28) Proof. The equation (28) can be deduced directly from Newton’s law: F(vOB1 ) = = d dτb [ m(vOB1 ) vOB1 ] and (26), or from (27) for cb = c that holds due to Ta = Tb implying µa = µb and therefore cb = c, (23). The equations (27) and (28) have been derived by starting with the time definition in Newton’s sense. 8. Energy and coordinate transformation. The expressions for the energy E of a body now result from its general expression E = mc2 and the expression for the corresponding mass depending on the body velocity vOB relative to the reference frame Tb × Rnb with respect to which the body mass at the rest is m0. The general case. Theorem 12. Let two identical particles 1 and 2 have the same mass m0 at the rest relative to a reference coordinate system T ×Rn. Let another two coordinate systems Ta ×Rna and Tb ×Rnb be accepted, Ta 6= Tb. Let the space coordinate system Rna be the “centre-of-mass” frame for the particle 1 and a particle 2. Let the particle 2 be at the rest relative to Rnb . Let the space coordinate system Rnb be at the rest relative to Rn. Then, the energy E(vOB1 ) of the particle 1 moving with the speed vOB1 = vOB1 r0 = vOB1 (τb; τb0)r0 is related to its mass m0 and to its energy E0 = m0c 2 when it is at the rest relative to Rnb by 482 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 E(vOB1 ) = m0(cb)2√√√√1− ( vOB1 cb )2 = ( cb c )2 E0√√√√1− ( vOB1 cb )2 . (29) Proof. The equation (29) follows directly from E(vOB1 ) = m(vOB1 )(cb)2 and (24). The special case. Theorem 13. Let two identical particles 1 and 2 have the same mass m0 at the rest relative to a reference coordinate system T ×Rn. Let another two coordinate systems Ta ×Rna and Tb ×Rnb be accepted so that Ta = Tb. Let the space coordinate system Rna be the “centre-of-mass” frame. Let the space coordinate system Rnb be at the rest relative to Rn. Then, the energy E(vOB1 ) of the particle 1 moving with the speed vOB1 = vOB1 r0 = vOB1 (τb; τb0)r0 is related to its mass m0 and to is energy E0 when it is at the rest relative to Rnb by: E(vOB1 ) = m0c 2√√√√1− ( vOB1 c )2 = E0√√√√1− ( vOB1 c )2 . (30) Proof. The equation (30) can be deduced directly from E(vOB1 ) = m(vOB1 )(cb)2, (26) and cb = c, or from (29) for cb = c. The equations (29) and (30) have been derived by starting with the time definition in Newton’s sense. 9. Time, physical continuity and uniqueness principle, and control. In order for a mathemati- cal description of a physical system to be adequate it is necessary (but not sufficient) that all the system variables obey the Physical Continuity and Uniqueness Principle, which is accepted to hold for the following mathematical model: dx(t) dt = f [x(t), d(t)] +B[x(t)]u(t; ·), rankB(x) = n for all x ∈ Rn, (31) where x ∈ Rn, f(·) : Rn ×Rd → Rn, d(·) : R→ Rd, B(·) : Rn → Rn×r, u(·) : R× · · · → Rr. It is demanded that every system motion x(.;x0; d;u), x(t;x0; d;u) ≡ x(t), tracks elementwi- se with a requested tracking quality any system desired motion xd(·) ∈ Sx for arbitrary perturbation vector function d(·) ∈ Sd. The requested tracking quality can be defined by properties of solutions to the following vector equation: h e(i)(t), . . . , e(t), t∫ 0 e(t)dt  = 0 (32) for all t ≥ 0, h(·) : Rn × · · · ×Rn → Rn, i ∈ {1, 2, . . .} , where e(·) is the error vector function, e(t) = xd(t)− x(t). ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 483 Real forms of the vector functions f(·) and d(·) are unknown as well as their real instantaneous vector values. However the matrix function B(·) ant the vector function h(·) are completely known. The state vector x(t) is elementwise measurable. A control is self-adaptive tracking control for system (31) if and only if it guarantees that the system exhibits with the requested quality elementwise tracking of any its desired motion xd(·) ∈ Sx for arbitrary perturbation vector function d(·) ∈ Sd, and that it can be synthesised and implemented without using any information about real forms and vector values of f(·) and d(·), but by using information about h(·), e(·), x(·) and possibly about a subsidiary matrix function C(·) : Rn → Rr×n in order to ensure an appropriate error vector to control vector vector channelling. The self-adaptive tracking control u(·) is natural tracking control if and only if the subsidiary matrix function C(·) is not used for its synthesis and implementation. Let u(t−) ≡ u(t− ε) for ε sufficiently small : 0 < ε < 1 or for ε→ 0+.In the ideal case ε = 0+. Theorem 14. (a) Let all variables of system (31) obey Physical Continuity and Uniqueness Principle. In order for a control u(·) to be in the ideal case or in the case ε is sufficiently small a self-adaptive tracking control for the system on Sd × Sx ensuring a requested tracking quality defined by (32) it is both necessary and sufficient that: u[t, e(t), x(t)] = u[t−, e(t−), x(t−)]+ +C[x(t)] {B[x(t)]C[x(t)]}−1 h e(i)(t), . . . , e(t), t∫ 0 e(t) dt  , (33) where C(·) : Rn → Rr×n is any matrix obeying elementwise the Physical Continuity and Uni- queness Principle and detB(x)C(x) 6= 0 for all x ∈ Rn. C(x) ≡ BT (x) is the additional necessary and sufficient condition for the control u(·) (33) to be the natural tracking control. Proof. Necessity. Let all variables of system (31) obey the Physical Continuity and Uni- queness Principle and let a control u(·) be (in the ideal case or in the case ε is sufficiently small) a self-adaptive tracking control for system (31) on Sd×Sx ensuring a requested tracking quality defined by (32). The equation (31) can be written also as: dx(t−) dt = f [x(t−), d(t−)] +B[x(t−)]u(t−; ·), or together with (32), dx(t−) dt = f [x(t−), d(t−)] +B[x(t−)]u(t−; ·) + h e(i)(t), . . . , e(t), t∫ 0 e(t) dt  . The equation (31) can be subtracted from this equation: dx(t−) dt − dx(t) dt = f [x(t−), d(t−)]− f [x(t), d(t)] +B[x(t−)]u(t−; ·)− − B[x(t)]u(t; ·) + h e(i)(t), . . . , e(t), t∫ 0 e(t) dt  . (34) 484 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 Since all the variables obey the Physical Continuity and Uniqueness Principle then, in the ideal case or in the case ε is sufficiently small, due to time continuity: dx(t−) dt ≡ dx(t) dt and f [x(t−), d(t−)] ≡ f [x(t), d(t)] so that equation (34) reduces to: B[x(t)]u(t; ·) = B[x(t−)]u(t−; ·) + h e(i)(t), . . . , e(t), t∫ 0 e(t) dt  . (35) Let C(·) : Rn → Rr×n be such that detB(x)C(x) 6= 0 for all x ∈ Rn that is possible due to detB(x) 6= 0 for all x ∈ Rn, and let u(t; ·) = C[x(t)]w(t; ·) so that w(; ·) well defines u(t; ·). Such a determination of u(t; ·) and the definition of C(·) transform (35) into w[t, e(t), x(t)] = {B[x(t)]C[x(t)]}−1 {B[x(t−)]C[x(t−)] } w[t−, e(t−), x(t−)]+ + {B[x(t)]C[x(t)]}−1 h e(i)(t), . . . , e(t), t∫ 0 e(t) dt  , which can be set in the next form implied by B[x(t)]C[x(t)] ≡ B[x(t−)]C[x(t−)] ensured by the Physical Continuity and Uniqueness Principle, by time continuity and by non-singularity of B(·)C(·): w[t, e(t), x(t)] = w[t−, e(t−), x(t−)]+ + {B[x(t)]C[x(t)]}−1 h e(i)(t), . . . , e(t), t∫ 0 e(t) dt  . After multiplying this equation by C[x(t)] on the left and by using u(t; ·) = C[x(t)]w(t; ·) we prove (33). Let now the control u(·) (33) be natural tracking control. Hence, an additional matrix C(x) is not used, which implies C(x) ≡ BT (x). Sufficiency. Let all conditions ant the statement of the theorem to be proved hold. Then (33) and (31) result in: dx(t) dt = f [x(t), d(t)] +B[x(t−)]u(t−; ·) + h e(i)(t), . . . , e(t), t∫ 0 e(t) dt  or, by using (31) for t− in order to replace B[x(t−)]u(t−) by dx(t−) dt − f [x(t−), d(t−)] in the preceding equation, we find: dx(t) dt = f [x(t), d(t)] + dx(t−) dt − f [x(t−), d(t−)] + h e(i)(t), . . . , e(t), t∫ 0 e(t) dt  , ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 485 which results in: 0 = h e(i)(t), . . . , e(t), t∫ 0 e(t) dt  , (36) due to dx(t−) dt ≡ dx(t−) dt and f [x(t−, d(t−)] ≡ f [x(t), d(t)] guaranteed by the Physical Continuity and Uniqueness Principle, by continuity of time and by sufficiently small ε. The equation (36) proves that the system exhibits the requested tracking property. Evidently, C(x) ≡ BT (x) can be accepted due to rank B(x) ≡ n. In such a case an additional matrix C(x) is not used to synthesise the control u(·) (33), which is therefore the natural tracking control for the system. 10. Conclusion. The essential features of time are explained in Newton’s sence: time is a physical variable the value of which (called: moment or instant) has been strictly monotonously increasing independently of all other variables, processes, movements and events. For this reason Newton explained the absolute sense and meaning of time. However, Newton himself explained also a relative sense, meaning and use of time by introducing different time units and scales in order to measure the time values and their difference (time intervals). The time values are used to determine the order of happenings of events, processes and/or movements. A time interval is used to measure a duration of a process, of a movement or of a rest. Time evolution expresses the ageing process. Ageing speeds can be different not only for different processes, objects, systems, but also for different parts of the same process, object, system. Different ageing speeds can imply different time scales and units. This can create an incorrect impression, feelingt and/or interpretation of “different times” instead of the correct conclusion: “different time units and/or different time scales”. Such Newton’s understanding of time was used at first to generalize the Lorentz transformation [65, 66], which has bee exploited herein to prove new results on velocity, acceleration, mass and energy of a moving body, and on a force causing its movement. The new relationships are more general than those existing in the relativity theory. The former incorporates the latter. It has been also shown that by using the real features of time as explai- ned essentially by Newton and in more details herein, we are able to deduce all the basic relati- onships of the relativity theory and to show that they correspond to a special, singular case. Moreover, such Newton’s understanding of time gives a fundamental importance to a new physical principle: Physical Continuity and Uniqueness Principle discovered recently [67 – 70] and explained in the paper. Their combination is the basis of a new concept of control of techni- cal objects, which just reflects how the Nature creates a control. The essence of such a control called natural (tracking) control, or self-adaptive control, is explained in the paper by provi- ng the corresponding control algorithm. One of its characteristics is the use of information about the error by closing a global negative feedback and about the just realised control by closing a local positive unit feedback. The former ensures a requested tracking property to the controlled system, i.e. it guarantees the requested tracking quality. The latter compensates unknown, unpredictable variations of the object internal dynamics and of actions of also unknown, unpredictable external disturbances. Hence, the natural (tracking) controller does not use any information about the mathematical model of the object internal dynamics and about external disturbances in order to generate the control. As the Nature does. 486 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 1. Mishchenko E.F., Kolesov Yu.S., Kolesov A.Yu., Rozov N.Kh. Asymptotic methods in singularly perturbed systems. — New York: Consultants Bureau, 1994. 2. Naidu D.S. Singular perturbation methodology in control systems. — London: Peter Peregrinus Ltd., 1988. 3. O’Malley R.E. (Jr.). Introduction to singular perturbations. — New York: Acad. Press, 1974. 4. Prigogine I. Etude thermodynamique des Phénomenes Irréversibles. — Paris: Dunod, 1947. 5. Prigogine I. Non-equilibrium statistical mechanics. — New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1962. 6. Smith D.R. Singular-perturbation theory. — Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1985. 7. Tikhonov A.N. Systems of differential equations containing small parameters in the derivatives // Math. Sb. — 1952. — 31. — P. 576 – 586 (in Russian). 8. Grujić Lj.T., Martynyuk A.A., Ribbens-Pavella M. Large scale systems stability under structural and singular perturbations. — Berlin: Springer, 1987. 9. Newton I. Mathematical principles of natural philosophy. Book 1. The motion of bodies / (Ed. 1687) W. Benton. — Chicago: Publisher, Encyclopaedia Britannica, Inc., 1952. 10. Luminet J.-P. Matiére, espace, temps // Le temps et sa Fléche (J. T. T. Vân, Dir.). — Paris: Frontières, 1994. — P. 59 – 80. 11. Kalman R.E., Falb P.L., Arbib M.A. Topics in mathematical system theory. — New York: McGraw Hill, 1969. 12. Michel A.N., Hou L. Modeling and qualitative theory for general hybrid dynamical and control systems / Preprints IFAC-IFIP-IMACS Conf. ”Control of Industrial Systems", Belfort, France, (20 – 22 May 1997). — 1997. — P. 173 – 183. 13. Atmanspacher H., Ruhnau E. Time, temporality now. — Berlin: Springer, 1997. 14. Davies P.C.W. The physics of time asymmetry. — Berkeley: California Press, 1974. 15. Eddington A.S. The nature of the physical world. — New York: Macmillan Comp., 1940. 16. Gold T. The arrow of time // Amer. J. Phys. — 1962. — 30. — P. 403 – 410. 17. Gouguenheim L. Méthodes de l’astrophysique. Comment connaitre et comprendre l’univers. — Paris: Hachette, 1981. 18. Hawking S.W. Une bréve histoire du temps. Du Big Bang aux trous noirs. — Paris: Flammarion, 1989. 19. Hawking S.W., Ellis G.F.R. The large scale structure os space-time. — Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1991. 20. Mehlberg H. Physical laws and time’s arrow // Curr. Issues in Phil. Sci. (Proc. Sect. L Amer. Assoc. Adv. Sci.). — New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1961. — P. 104 – 138. 21. Merleau-Ponty J., Morando B. Les trois étapes de la cosmologie. — Paris, 1971. 22. Nevanlinna R. Raum, Zeit und Relativitat. — Basel: Birkhäuserverlag, 1964. 23. Prigogine I. From being to becoming. Time and complexity in the physical sciences. — San Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Copm., 1980. 24. Reichenbach H. The direction of time. — Berkeley: Univ. California Press, 1991. 25. Robb A. Geometry of time and space. — Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1936. 26. Schrödinger E. Space-time structure. — Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1954. 27. Zeh H.-D. The physical basis of the direction of time. — Berlin: Springer, 1989. 28. Conche M. Temps et destin. — Paris: Pres. Univ. France, 1992. 29. Eddington A. The phylosophy of physical science. — Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1939. 30. Grünbaum A. Philosophical problems of space and time. — London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1963. 31. Hill E.L. Quantum physics and the relativity theory // Curr. Issues in Phil. Sci. (Proc. Sect. L Amer. Assoc. Adv. Sci.). — New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1961. — P. 429 – 441. 32. Klein E. Le temps. — Paris: Dominos, Flammarion, 1995. 33. Prigogine I., Stengers I. La nouvelle alliance. — France: Gallimard, 1979. ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 487 34. Reichenbach H. The philosophy of space & time. — New York: Dover Publ., Inc., 1958. 35. The concepts of space and time / Ed. M. Čapek. — Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publ. Comp., 1976. 36. Paty M. Sur l’histoire du probléme du temps. Le temps physique et les phénomènes // Temps et Flèche. — Paris: Frontières, 1994. — P. 21 – 58. 37. Lorentz H.A. Versuch einer Theorie der elektrischen und optischen Erscheinungen in bewegten Körpern. — Leiden: E. K. Brill, 1895. 38. Lorentz H.A. Das Relativitätsprinzip. — Leipzig: B. G. Teubner, 1914. 39. Lorentz H.A. The theory of electrons. — Leipzig: B. G. Teubner, 1916. 40. Lorentz H.A. Deux mémoires de Henri Poincaré sur la physique mathématique // Acta math. — 1921. — 38. — P. 294 – 308. 41. Lorentz H.A., Einstein A., Minkowski H. Das Relativitätsprinzip. — Leipzig: B. G. Teubner, 1923. 42. Poincaré H. Sur la dynamique de l’électron // C. r. Acad. sci. Paris. — 1905. — P. 1504 – 1508; Rend. Circ. mat. Palermo. — 1906. — 21. — P. 130 – 176. 43. Einstein A. La théorie de la relativité. — Paris: Gauthier-Villars et Cie, 1921. 44. Einstein A. Léther et la théorie de la relativité. — Paris: Gauthier-Villars et Cie, 1921. 45. Einstein A. The meaning of relativity. — London: Methuen & Comp., Ltd., 1950. 46. Einstein A. Relativity / Univ. paperbacks. — London: Methuen & Comp., Ltd., 1960. 47. Einstein A., Infeld L. L’évolution des idées en physique. — Paris: Flammarion, 1938. 48. Adler R., Bazin M., Schiffer M. Introduction to general relativity. — Tokyo: McGraw Hill Kogakusha, Ltd., 1975. 49. Das A. The special theory of relativity. — New York: Springer, 1993. 50. Eddington A.S. The mathematical theory of relativity. — New York: Chelsea Publ., Comp., 1975. 51. Lorentz H.A., Einstein A., Minkowski H., Weyl H. The principle of relativity. — New York: Dover Publ., Inc., 1952. 52. D’Inverno R. Introducing Einstein’s relativity. — Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995. 53. Fock V. The theory of space // Time and Gravitation. — London: Pergamon Press, 1959. 54. Foster J., Nightingale J.D. A short course in general relativity. — New York: Springer, 1995. 55. Kouznétsov B. Essais sur la relativité. — Moscou: Mir, 1971. 56. Mach A. La physique moderne et ses théories. — New York: Gallimard, Random House, 1962. 57. Ougarov V. Théorie de la relativité restreinte. — Moscou: Mir, 1969. 58. Prokhovnik S.J. Logique de la relativité restreinte. — Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1969. 59. Russell B. ABC de la relativié // Le Monde en 10/18. — Saint – Amand: Union Général d’Editions, 1965. 60. Schlick M. Space and time in contemporary physics. — New York: Dover Publ., Inc., 1963. 61. Tonnelat M.-A. Histoire du principle de relativité. — Paris: Flammarion, 1971. 62. Wald R.M. Space, time and gravity. — Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press, 1992. 63. De Beauregard O.C. Mesure du temps et relativité // Cah. Phys. — 1958. — 95. — P. 256 – 260. 64. Yourgrau W. Some problems concerning fundamental constants in physics // Curr. Issues in Phil. Sci. (Proc. Sect. L Amer. Assoc. Adv. Sci.). — New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1961. — P. 319 – 342. 65. Grujić Lj.T. Time and modeling // Proc. 1996 IEEE Int. Conf. Systems, Man and Cybernetics, Beijing. — 1996. — 3. — P. 2438 – 2443. 66. Grujić Lj.T. Multiple time scale systems, time and modeling. — Preprints IFAC-IMACS-IFIP Conf. Contr. Ind. Syst. (Belfort, France). — 1997. — 1. — P. 293 – 298; Proc. IFAC Conf. Contr. Ind. Syst. (Pergamon, Elsevier). — 1997. — 1. — P. 189 – 194. 67. Gruyitch Ly.T. Physical continuity and uniqueness principle. Exponential natural tracking control // J. Neural, Parallel and Sci. Comput. — 1998. — 6, № 2. — P. 143 – 170. 488 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 68. Gruyitch Ly.T. Exponential stabilizing natural tracking control of robots: theory // Proc. ROBOTICS 98, Albuquerque, USA, April 26 – 30, 1998. — P. 286 – 292. 69. Gruyitch Ly.T. Vector Lyapunov function synthesis of aircraft control // Proc. II Int. Conf. Nonlinear Probl. in Aviation and Aerospace, Daytona Beach, USA, 29 April — 1 May, 1998. — To appear. 70. Gruyitch Ly.T. Natural tracking control synthesis for Lagrangian systems // Proc. V Int. Sem. Stability and Oscillations of Nonlinear Control Systems, Inst. Control Problems, Rus. Acad. Sci., Moskow, June 3 – 5, 1998. — P. 115 – 120. 71. Grujić Lj.T., Mounfield W.P. Natural tracking control of linear systems // Proc. 13th World Congr. Comput. and Appl. Math., IMACS’91, Dublin, Ireland. — 1991. — 3. — P. 1269 – 1270. 72. Grujić Lj.T., Mounfield W.P. Natural tracking control of time-invariant linear systems described by I/O // Different. Equat. (Proc. 30th IEEE CDC, Brigthon, England). — 1991. — 3. — P. 2441 – 2446. 73. Grujić Lj.T., Mounfield W.P. Natural tracking control of linear systems // Math. Analysis and Design of Process Control. Elsev. Sci. Publ. B. V., IMACS, 1992. — P. 53 – 64. 74. Grujić Lj.T., Mounfield W.P. Stablewise tracking with finite reachability time: linear time-invariant continuous-time MIMO systems // Proc. 31 st IEEE Conf. Decision and Control, Tucson, Arizona. — 1992. — P. 834 – 839. 75. Grujić Lj.T., Mounfield W.P. PD-control for stablewise tracking with finite reachability time: linear conti- nuous time MIMO systems with state-space description // Int. J. Robust and Nonlinear Control. — 1993. — 3. — P. 341 – 360. 76. Mounfield W.P., Grujić Lj.T. Natural tracking control of linear systems // Proc. 13th World Congr. Comput. and Appl. Math., IMACS’91, Dublin, Ireland. — 1991. — 3. — P. 1269 – 1270. 77. Mounfield W.P., Grujić Lj.T. High-gain natural tracking control of time-invariant systems described by I/O // Differnt. Equat., (Proc. 30th IEEE CDC, Brigthon, England). — 1991. — 3. — P. 2447 – 2452. 78. Mounfield W.P., Grujić Lj.T. High-gain PI natural control for exponential tracking of linear single-output systems with state-space description // RAIRO APII — Théorie de la commande. — 1992. — P. 125 – 146. 79. Mounfield W.P., Grujić Lj.T. Natural tracking control for exponential tracking : lateral high-gain PI control of an aircraft system with state-space description // Neural, Parallel & Sci. Comput. — 1993. — 1, № 3. — P. 357 – 370. 80. Mounfield W.P., Grujić Lj.T. High-gain PI natural tracking control for exponential tracking of linear MIMO systems with-state-space description // Int. J. Systems Sci. — 1994. — 25, № 11. — P. 1793 – 1817. Received 13.04.99 ISSN 1562-3076. Нелiнiйнi коливання, 1999, т. 2, № 4 489